Review by Neil Vickers
Nassir GhaemiÕs book The
Rise and Fall of the Biopsychosocial Model (2009) is about the
biopsychosocial model of health and disease as it is used in psychiatry. In GhaemiÕs view, at least in the English-speaking world,
psychiatry has always been implicitly eclectic. Of course, some psychiatrists
rejected eclecticism in favour of a single form of treatment such as
psychoanalysis, or psychopharmacology, or electroconvulsive therapy. But
psychiatryÕs status as a medical specialty has always been predicated on the
idea that it was broadly-based: it was not necessary to attach oneself to any
particular school of thought about mental illness in order to use the title of
psychiatrist. More positively, this diversity was often said to correspond to
the peculiar characteristics of mental illnesses. On this view, there is no
unified field theory that unites all the concepts and information needed in
psychiatric practice because some mental illnesses are thought to stem from the
patientÕs outlook on his life, some the result of genes, and others still of
the interaction of genes and experience. To complicate matters further,
psychiatrists disagree amongst themselves about which disorders belong in which
categories. Ghaemi sees the biopsychosocial model as
a set of truisms that enables psychiatrists to ignore the significance of these
disagreements. Everybody believes that biology, psychology and the social world
have a bearing on mental health. The biopsychosocial model is a way of not
mentioning the war.
Ghaemi is at his most persuasive when setting
the biopsychosocial model in the context of earlier solutions to this problem
which has dogged psychiatry more or less since its inception. Not only are
there major disagreements about mental illnesses in general and in particular,
there is no way of bridging the gaps that commands sufficiently wide support
within psychiatry, other than by saying that everyoneÕs on to something. In GhaemiÕs narrative, the rot set in with Adolf MeyerÕs
psychobiology. Meyer believed that in psychiatry you have to treat the whole
person. You took a detailed case history paying close attention to the biological,
psychological, and social factors relevant to the patientÕs symptoms. He was
especially interested in the ways in which the patientÕs social and
environmental background might predispose him to react pathologically to
certain life events. Most
mental illnesses, in his view, were reactions to life events. Ghaemi points out that Meyer did not reject biology; but
Meyer didnÕt pursue the biological causes of mental illness through his own
research, even though he encouraged others to do so. Phillip Slavney and Paul McHugh note that Ôfor Meyer the person was
a level of biological organisation just as important as the molecular or the
cellular. Functioning at each level has its own rules and should be studied on
its own terms.Õ It should be borne in mind that in MeyerÕs psychobiology,
functioning at each level would be studied by distinct disciplines. Biologists
and physiologists would study anatomical lesions and toxic factors,
psychologists would study personality traits, cultural influences,
environmental stressors and the like. In some respects Meyer was a forerunner
of Karl Ludwig von BertalanffyÕs general systems theory (GST), which
was very compatible with MeyerÕs outlook. GST was the study of systems in
general. Perhaps what distinguishes GST most from MeyerÕs
theory was a more flexible account of the subsystems that defined the whole. In
Von BerlalanffyÕs work, the hierarchical levels of
functioning were not necessarily coterminous with specific academic disciplines.
Nevertheless, Ghaemi is right to echo a point made by
Paul McHugh that the biopsychosocial model is ÔAdolf MeyerÕs concept of
psychobiology renamed and reanimated for the contemporary eraÕ (2006). Roy Grinker and George Engel, the two men who Ghaemi thinks did most to establish and disseminate the
biopsychosocial model in its current form, were strongly committed to Von BertalanffyÕs ideas about systems and both acknowledged
MeyerÕs foundational role. For Grinker, the
psychiatrist and the psychoanalyst were trying to understand Ôthe
psycho-somatic-environmental systems as processes in transaction, within a
particular universe or field.Õ Engel too presented health and disease in terms
of a hierarchy of systems culminating in the biosphere into which were subsumed
society, culture, community, family, the person all the way down to sub-atomic
particles by way of the nervous system, the vital organs and body tissue.
The
biopsychosocial model was not devised in response to a problem in mainstream
psychiatry at all. It came out of psychosomatic medicine, a discipline in which
there was great openness to psychoanalytic ideas but which was not exclusively
psychoanalytic. On page 53, Ghaemi concedes
that Ôthe main source of the
BPS model is psychosomatic medicine, concerned with medical illnesses with
psychological componentsÕ. He continues: ÔIt has been little discussed whether
a model derived from this small corner of the psychiatric profession is
appropriate for the entire broad range of mental illnesses.Õ I will come to the
second point later on. The first warrants more detailed exploration than Ghaemi gives it. The
biopsychosocial model was elaborated as a way of conceptualising the vicissitudes
of internal experience of illness. Above
all else, it was an attempt to study the ways in which the patientÕs personhood
contributes to the unfolding of pathological processes. It is a major
weakness of GhaemiÕs book is that he refuses to
engage with this idea. By turns he says itÕs something doctors know already or
he treats it as a form of eclecticism that puts medicine on the same level as
psychology and sociology. But that is not how the founders, all of whom were
medically qualified, saw it.
This brings me
to an aside. On the subject of the founders, Ghaemi
is eccentric, to put it mildly. He thinks the term Ôthe biopsychosocial modelÕ
ought to be credited to Roy Grinker because Grinker almost
used the term in 1952. Moreover, Ghaemi insinuates
that when he wrote his famous paper of 1977 Engel must have known about GrinkerÕs priority but chose not to acknowledge him. Ghaemi awards Grinker priority on
the basis of a paper entitled ÔTraining of a psychiatrist-psychoanalystÕ which
was given as a presentation to the Chicago Psychoanalytic Institute but which
wasnÕt published until 1994. (Engel wasnÕt present when it was first read out.)
In this paper Grinker describes body, mind and
society as a unity and invokes the Ôpsycho-somatic-socialÕ as a near synonym. Here
is the passage in full:
[The
psychiatrist and the psychoanalyst] are practitioners in a field of behavior in
which they try to understand the psycho-somatic-environmental systems as
processes in transaction, within a particular universe or field. The
psychiatrist or analyst is usually interested most intensely in varying levels
of the psychic system. The physiologist or physician penetrates into the depths
of activities of the somatic system. The sociologist is more concerned with the
interaction of individuals as total persons within various social or
environmental settings. It is not possible for any person to fully understand a
system from its structural analysis attained by working inside that system
alone, however. One can learn more about interrelations between somatic and
psychic or between psychic and social systems by making observations at the
boundaries of their interactions. In order to understand more adequately the
processes at work in the total psycho-somatic-social field, however, one must
understand the processes that go on in transaction among at least three systems
by assuming a more distant position outside the system but within the field.
The point seems
well made. But in 1945 George Engel and John Romano called for a Ômore
comprehensive frame of reference or conceptual scheme of disease [than that]
with which the student had heretofore been ... familiar ... [a] conceptual
scheme ... in which psychologic and social factors
exist or coexist with more impersonal biologic factors, eventually to cause,
provoke, or otherwise modify variations in the total human biologic behavior.Õ If
near misses count, why do Engel and Romano not get priority? If Ghaemi had given the history of psychosomatic medicine its
proper weight, he would have known that it was founded on the idea of a link
between the biological, the psychological and the social. Grinker
first used the term Ôthe biopsychosocial modelÕ in 1962, some eight years after
Nathan Ackerman used it in 1954 (in a paper entitled ÔSome Structural Problems
in the Relations of Psychoanalysis and Group PsychotherapyÕ (International Journal of Group Psychotherapy
(Jan 1, 1954): 131-146). It was also used in two papers by F. A. Weiss in 1958.
In short, the case for GrinkerÕs priority is not
credible.
Focusing who was
first to use the word or the phrase impoverishes the historical context. But the
context is both rich and relevant. The biopsychosocial model was not just an
aspiration, it was embodied in a programme of research and it is as a research
programme that Ghaemi should have considered it. He mentions
a few projects, notably EngelÕs study of a baby named Monika who was born with an oesophageal atresia, which meant she had to be fed through
a surgically produced gastric fistula during the first two years of her life. In the United States, psychosomatic
medicine in the 1930s was associated with Walter Cannon who was no Freudian. By
the forties, psychoanalysis had made it its own. At this point the leading
figures were Helen Flanders Dunbar and Franz Alexander, who was one of three
psychoanalysts to psychoanalyse Roy Grinker, the
other two being Freud himself and Therese Benedek. In
1932 Alexander set up the Chicago Institute of Psychoanalysis, independently of
the American Psychoanalytic Association. Unlike every other psychoanalytic
institute in the world, the Chicago Institute was not specifically focused on
mental health. Instead, trainees were invited to study the role of
psychic factors, especially emotions, in bodily disturbances. GrinkerÕs 1952 paper in which he posits a unity of body,
mind and social world was given to AlexanderÕs Institute and begins with a
fulsome tribute to him. Alexander believed there were psychological
determinants of duodenal ulcers, a research programme
Ghaemi ridicules, citing the discovery of the Heliobacter Pylorus. Grinker practised conventional five-times-a-week
analysis for many years. Engel never did. Ghaemi
concedes that Engel came to psychoanalysis slowly but he pays almost no
attention to his pre-psychoanalytic research in psychosomatics. In the
above-mentioned paper, Theodore M. Brown has documented the extent of EngelÕs
involvement in psychosomatic medicine between 1938 when he got his first
hospital job and 1946 when he began his training analysis. He shows that until
1942, Engel was hostile to Freudian ideas.
If Ghaemi had followed Engel through a single one of his
studies he might have understood the biopsychosocial model better. Ghaemi likes to quote recent writersÕ definitions but
EngelÕs contribution is presented in a few summary sentences. Even less
defensible is the attribution to Engel of positions he never advances such as
the claim – culled from Giovanni Fava in 2005 - that all disorders have
multiple, co-occurring and distinct bio, psycho and social determinants. At a
minimum, it is essential to distinguish the biopsychosocial model in clinical
practice from the biopsychosocial model in research. The two are of course
related but the second cannot be read off from the first. Like all theories
rooted in a notion of the whole person, the biopsychosocial model in clinical
research looks at the course of an individualÕs life. Engel and Franz Reichsman – another internist-psychoanalyst –
carried out a longitudinal study of Monica that lasted 40 years. They were
interested in understanding better the physiology of the mother-infant
relationship. In this their work invites comparison with BowlbyÕs work on
attachment and maternal deprivation or even Harry HarlowÕs experiments on
monkeys separated at birth from their mothers. When Monica was 15-monthsÕ old
she was readmitted to hospital having failed to bond with her mother who was
then 20. She stayed in hospital for nine months during which time she became
attached to Reichsman and one of the
nurses, both of whom in turn became quite attached to her. During periods of
separation, Engel and Reichsman did cry but became
unresponsive and withdrawn. They observed a loss of muscle tone, profound
immobility, a sad facial expression. MonicaÕs gastric secretions ceased and
could not be stimulated using histamines. When Reichsman
or the nurse reappeared, MonicaÕs muscle tone returned, she moved about, showed
joy and her gastric secretion rates increased. Engel and Reichsman
named the complex of psychophysiological withdrawal a Ôdepression-withdrawal
reactionÕ. In a fine article on the evolution of EngelÕs psychoanalytic
thought, Graeme J. Taylor (who trained with Reichsman)
notes that Engel was wary of talking in terms of psychogenic causation.
However, in common with many researchers who have carried out studies of
attachment patterns since then Engel did think that Ôhidden within the
interactions between infant and mother are a number of processes by which the
mother serves as an external regulator not only of the infantÕs behaviour and
autonomic physiology, but also of the neurochemistry of its maturing brainÕ
(Taylor, 451). Ghaemi claims that ÔThere is not and never has been much
ÔBioÕ in the biopsychosocial model in psychiatryÕ (49). The Monica studies contradict
him.
Ghaemi presents EngelÕs
resistance to AlexanderÕs search for psychic causes of physical ailments as an
instance of his theoretical impotence. Unlike Grinker,
says Ghaemi, Engel hadnÕt a clue how to put together
the three parts of the biopsychosocial model but pretended he had through his
version of the biopsychosocial model, a name he took from Grinker
without acknowledgment. There is nothing fraudulent about noticing an
association before it can be understood in causal terms. And when associations
are demonstrated in areas that were hitherto not thought to be in play, they
deserve notice. Modern stress research – a very biopsychosocial field
– finds itself in a similar position. It demonstrates the ways in which
certain mental dispositions trigger physiological changes that begin in the
autonomic nervous system and the endocrine system and often affect the whole
body. Stress doesnÕt cause heart disease or diabetes. It exacerbates other biological weaknesses
that make one more vulnerable to those conditions. A physician treating a patient
with metabolic syndrome does not have to choose between the causes but can
attack them all, biopsychosocially.
GhaemiÕs determination to interpret the
biopsychosocial model narrowly as a treatment protocol enables him to
withhold from consideration biopsychosocial research in psychiatry. The entire
field of gene-environment epigenetic studies is biopsychosocial. The
interaction between serotonin transporter genotype and adverse environment in depressive
disorders is well established. But the association does not shed much light on
the causes of depressive disorder. Many researchers have suggested that chronic
stress results in overproduction of corticotropin-releasing
hormone by the hypothalamus and of the stress hormone cortisol by the adrenal
gland and that their combined action may underpin the interaction between serotonin
and adverse environment.
Monkeys are born
with either a long or a short version of the serotonin transporter gene
(5-HTLLP). Stephen Suomi and his colleagues at National Institute of Child
Health and Human Development (NICHD) in Bethesda, Maryland, looked at the
impact of mothering on serotonin metabolism in a large group of rhesus monkeys.
Half of the monkeys had been separated at birth from their mothers and been
reared by their peers. The other half were left with their mothers. At six
months, the peer-reared group were returned to their mothers. When the monkeys
were eight years old, Suomi and his colleagues identified the version of the
serotonin transporter gene that each monkey carried. They found that
peer-reared monkeys with the shorter version of the gene had poorer serotonin
metabolism than monkeys with the longer version but that mother-reared monkeys
with the short version did just as well as those with the longer version. In
other words, good mothering appears to ensure that monkeys with the
shorter version of the gene still metabolise
serotonin properly. This maternal buffering is an eminently biopsychosocial example
of a gene-environment interaction. With aggression itÕs even more interesting.
Monkeys with the short version of the serotonin transporter gene were more
aggressive than monkeys with the longer version but mother-reared monkeys with
the short version were least aggressive of all. If you look at alcohol
consumption the same thing is found. Monkeys with the short version of the
serotonin transporter gene were more likely to drink alcohol to excess than
monkeys with the longer version but mother-reared monkeys with the short
version were less likely to drink alcohol to excess than mother-reared monkeys
with the long version of the gene. In both these cases, what may be a genetic
risk factor for individuals with poor early experience may actually be a
genetic advantage in individuals with good early experience. For some
time, researchers looking at human mental health looked for associations
between the two variants of the gene and major mental health conditions. In the
Dunedin Longitudinal study (led by researchers at KingÕs College London and the
university of Otago!), Avshalom
Caspi and colleagues demonstrated that that humans
with the shorter version of the gene were more likely to suffer from depression
than those with the longer version but
only if they had higher levels of concurrent stress or if they had a history of
being maltreated. I could offer many more examples of biopsychosocial
research of this sort.
On page 60 of his book, Ghaemi quotes George
Davey Smith who stated that Ôwhile he thought that psychosocial factors were
relevant to the aetiology of many illnesses, especially psychiatric, they were
not yet shown to be Òdirect causesÓ but rather influences on the distribution of
known exposuresÓÕ. In support of this claim, Ghaemi
considers the example of H. Pylori.
Psychoanalytically-inclined practitioners of psychosomatic medicine were
convinced that there was a strong association between certain kinds of
personality and ulcers. But in 1983, Robert Warren and Barry Marshall
discovered H. Pylori and discovered
that it was the most common bacterium found in the human gut: about half of all
humans have it. Marshall conjectured that H.
Pylori actually causes the ulceration. Indeed, he demonstrated that it
could by infecting himself with it and suffering gastric inflammation as a
result. It is at this point that Ghaemi applies Davey
SmithÕs insight. ÔPerhaps social factor Z sometimes increases exposure to H. Pylori; even so, H. Pylori is still key to the causation of the illness and a major
point for intervention, while social factor Z is secondary and only
contributory to the extent that it that it affects exposure to H. PyloriÕ, he writes (61). ÔTo ignore
the ultimate biological cause may be counterproductiveÕ. (Why would a biopsychosocially-oriented physician want to ignore an
ultimate biological cause?) However, 15 per cent of those with duodenal ulcers
donÕt have H. Pylori in their gut. And only 10 per cent of those that do go on to develop duodenal
ulcers. So what else might be involved? Associations have been found
between ulcers and lifestyle habits such as alcohol consumption, smoking, and
not eating breakfast in the morning, all of which might be proxies for stress.
But according to Robert Sapolsky, there is evidence
that the biology of the stress response may also play a part. And what
initiates the stress response? GhaemiÕs social factor
Z. As Ghaemi surely knows, the field of epigenetics
of early life suggest that psychological experience can actually change a
personÕs biology. Suomi and his colleagues found that the structure of the
brains of their monkeys differed markedly at only 6 months of age. In 4,400 genes the two groups of monkeys exhibited
highly differentiated patterns of methylation. In other words, some genes were
switched on and some were switched, for the long term. The idea that the psycho
and social always play second fiddle to bio does not frame epigenetic research
on the long-term consequences of childhood trauma.
Ghaemi asks whether a theory derived from a Ôsmall corner of the psychiatric
profession is appropriate for the entire broad range of mental illnesses.Õ But
itÕs not a small corner now. The biopsychosocial model has broadened out
considerably since the 1930s to encompass attachment theory, most aspects of
human behavioural biology, phenomenology. What Ghaemi
really seems to object to is any departure from biomedically-oriented medicine. He waxes lyrical about
OslerÕs Ôclinico-pathological methodÕ in medicine in
which symptoms were related to underlying morbid anatomy post-mortem. Is that really a way forward for psychiatry? An answer
that a supporter of the biopsychosocial model might make is that the only way
to do good biomedical research is to take account of the impact of
psychological and social factors on biology.
Finally, there is the issue of the levels. It is not a
false problem but I canÕt see how it invalidates the biopsychosocial approach
generally. It may that the only way to disentangle the bio from the psycho and
the social is by doing research that considers all three. This is what has
happened in epigenetic research.